In 1759, Adam Smith, often hailed as the father of modern economics, published “The Theory of Moral Sentiments,” wherein he expounded upon the concept that societal evolution stems from “individual human action” rather than a predetermined “individual human design.” Smith argued that progress is facilitated through agreements grounded in trust and empathy between individuals. He believed that if people were free to engage in commerce and interactions based on these principles, society would naturally progress. Smith introduced the idea of the “Man of System,” a term for individuals who impose their vision of order on others, believing they know what is best. He critiqued this approach, noting it inevitably leads to failure because it disregards the truth that individuals will always strive for independent action regardless of imposed controls.
Smith’s critiques extend beyond individual examples to encapsulate broader societal structures. He observed this dynamic among religious leaders, educators, and political figures, all of whom often prioritize their narrative or framework over individual autonomy. Such leaders may either genuinely believe in their system or use their influence strategically, but ultimately, the imposition of their will disrupts the natural order of human interactions. Smith stressed that the failure of such systems is consistent: no single authority can truly account for the diverse motivations and needs of individuals, making attempts to control human behavior inherently flawed.
After “The Theory of Moral Sentiments,” Smith published “The Wealth of Nations” in 1776, significantly influencing the founding fathers of the United States. Central to Smith’s economic philosophy is the notion that wealth is generated by individuals pursuing their self-interest, which necessitates an innate understanding of empathy to foster trust. The founding fathers embraced these principles, emphasizing minimal government intervention while promoting free enterprise as the engine for societal growth. This approach contrasted sharply with the French Revolution, which, despite being inspired by the American model, ultimately failed to deliver the promised freedoms and instead replaced one form of autocracy with another.
Smith’s concept of the free market rests on voluntary exchanges, positing that producers will create goods based on what they believe will sell. Prices are determined not by decree but instead through the natural interplay of supply and demand. This system promotes a balance—wherein supply meets demand without coercion, allowing consumers and producers to operate freely. In a true free market, participants are neither forced to produce nor compelled to buy, fostering an ecosystem that is self-renewing and sustainable.
However, the influence of external forces, such as government interventions and trade unions, threatens to erode this “natural liberty.” Smith cautioned that their attempts to regulate prices, enjoin quotas, and impose taxation invariably lead to corruption, cronyism, and monopolistic practices. Governments, acting as the ultimate “Man of System,” disrupt the balance of free enterprise, often failing to understand the dynamic nature of market interactions. Their interventions tend to complicate rather than simplify market operations, spawning inefficiencies that harm the very individuals they claim to protect.
In contemporary discussions, capitalism and free enterprise are frequently blamed for societal issues, including poverty and subpar product quality. However, Smith argued that these problems stem not from the free market itself but from a century of government interference in market dynamics. True free markets, thriving in the absence of imposing controls, are capable of self-regulation to address the very issues critics cite. The objective of effective governance, according to Smith, is not to micromanage individual actions but to eliminate harmful interventions that hinder citizen autonomy. In summary, the fundamental lesson of Smith’s work is the recognition of individual human action’s potential when left unfettered by the constraints of the “Man of System.”